Subtitles section Play video Print subtitles Well, I’m speaking today with Dr. Stephen Hicks, who is a professor of philosophy in the Department of Philosophy at Rockford University in Illinois. Professor Hicks has written a book—he’s written several books—but he’s written one in particular that I wanted to talk to him about today called Explaining Postmodernism: Skepticism and Socialism from Rousseau to Foucault, which was published a fair while ago now, in 2004, but I think has become even more pertinent and relevant today. I have talked a lot to my viewers about your book, and so let’s talk about Postmodernism and its relationship with Neo-Marxism. So maybe you could tell the viewers here a little more about yourself and how you got interested in this. Well, I finished graduate school in philosophy in the early 90s, originally from Canada, born in Toronto. At that point Pittsburgh and Indiana had the two strongest philosophy of science and logic programs, and that’s what I was interested in at the time. And so upon a professor’s recommendation, I ended up at Indiana, and it worked out very nicely for me. So most of my graduate work was actually in epistemology, philosophy of science, logic, some cognitive science issues as well. So a lot of the epistemological and philosophical/linguistic issues that come up in Postmodernism—the groundwork so to speak was laid for that. When I finished grad school and started teaching full-time, came to Rockford University. I was teaching in an honors program, and the way that program worked was—it was essentially a Great Books program—and so it was like getting a second education, wonderfully. But the way it was done was that each course was taught by two professors to our honor students. So the professors would be from different departments, so I was paired with literature professors, history professors, and so on. And this was now the middle of the 90s. I started to hear about thinkers I had not read. I’d kind-of heard about them, but now I was reading them more closely and finding that in history and literature and sociology and anthropology, names like Derrida and Foucault and the others, if not omnipresent, were huge names. So I realized I had a gap in my education to fill. So I started reading deeply in them. My education in some ways was broad in the history of philosophy but narrow at the graduate school level and I had focused mostly on Anglo-American philosophy, so my understanding of the Continental traditions was quite limited. But by the time I got to the end of the 90s, I realized there was something significant going on coming out of Continental philosophy. And that’s where the book [published 2004] came out of. When you say significant, what do you mean by that? Do you mean intellectually? Do you mean socially? Politically? There’s lots of different variants of “significant.”When you say significant, what do you mean by that? Do you mean intellectually? Do you mean socially? Politically? There’s lots of different variants of “significant.” At that point, “intellectually.” This was still in the 1990s so postmodernism was not yet (outside of, say, art) a cultural force, but it was strongly an intellectual force in that. At that point, young Ph.D.s coming out of sociology, literary criticism, some sub-disciplines in the law (if you’re getting Ph.D. in the law), historiography and so on, and certainly in departments in philosophy still dominated by Continental traditional philosophy: almost all of them are primarily being schooled in what we now call postmodern thinkers, so the leading gurus are people like Derrida, Lyotard, from whom we get the label post-modern condition, Foucault and the others. So maybe you could walk us through what you learned, because people are unfamiliar ... I mean, you were advanced in your education, including in philosophy, and still recognized your ignorance, say, with regards to postmodern thinking, so that’s obviously a condition that is shared by a large number of people. Postmodernism is one of those words like Existentialism that covers an awful lot of territory, and so maybe we could zero in on exactly what that means, and who these thinkers were: Derrida, Foucault, and Lyotard, and what you learned about them. Fair enough. Well, all of the thinkers you just named—they think broadly, they think strategically, and they do have a very strong historical perspective on their disciplines, and at the same time they are trying to assess where they think we are culturally, politically, socially—and all of them are making a very dramatic claim: that to some extent or in some way Modernism has either ended or it has reached its nadir, or all of the … kind of the pathologies and negative traits within the modern world are reaching a culmination in their generation, and so it’s time for us to both recognize that Modernism has come to an end, and that we need some sort of new intellectual framework, a post-modern-like framework. And the Modernism that they’re criticizing, how would you characterize that? That’s Enlightenment values? Scientific rationalism? How would you characterize it, exactly? All of those would be elements of it. But then of course there are some discipline-specific differences: so literature people and philosophy people and historians will use Modernism slightly differently. But the idea at core is that if you look at the pre-modern world—essentially the world of the Middle Ages, say—that that was itself broken up by a series of revolutions: the Renaissance, Reformation, Counter Reformation, early scientific revolutions—and all of this is going on in historically short chunks of time: 1500s and 1600s. And so if you look at both the intellectual world and the social world, comparing, say, the 1400s with the 1700s, culturally and intellectually you’re in a different universe at that point. So the features then of the modern world—now I’m going to use my philosophical labels here—are that we are now naturalistic in our thinking. We are no longer primarily supernaturalistic in our thinking. So we might still be open to the idea that there’s a God or some sort of supernatural dimension, the way Deists are, but first and foremost we’re taking the natural world as a more or less self-contained, self-governing world that operates according to cause and effect, and we’re going to study it in its terms. We’re not seeing the natural world as derivative of a “higher” world or that everything that happens in the natural world is part of “God’s plan” where we read omens and so forth into everything. So metaphysically then there’s been a revolution: We’re naturalistic. Epistemologically—in terms of knowledge—there also has been a revolution. How do we know the important truths? How do we acquire the beliefs that we’re fundamentally going to commit our lives to? Well, by the time we become Moderns we take experience seriously, personal experience. We do that more rigorously and we’re developing scientific method (the way of organizing the data), we’re taking logic and all the sophisticated tools of rationality and developing those increasingly ... And so our opposition then is: Either you know something because you can experience it and verify it for yourself, or we've done the really hard work of scientific method and as a result of what comes out of that, that’s what we can call knowledge or our best approximation to that. And that’s also revolutionary because the prior intellectual framework was much more intellectually authoritarian in its framework. You would accept in the Catholic tradition the authority of the Church. And who are you to question the authority of the Church? And who are you to mouth empirical-rational arguments against the authority of the Church? Or, you take the authority of Scripture, or you accept on faith that you've had a mystical revelation of some sort. So, in all of those cases you have non-rational epistemologies that are dominating intellectual discourse. That is all by and large swept away in the modern world. Okay, so prior to the emergence of the modern world, we’ll say, people are dominated essentially by their willingness to adhere to a shared tradition and that shared tradition is somewhat tyrannically enforced. But there’s no real alternative in terms of epistemology [epistemology: the theory of knowledge, especially with regard to its methods, validity and scope: the investigation of what distinguishes justified belief from opinion] let’s say. And then as the modern world emerges, people discover the technologies of science and the value of rigorously applied method and the comparison of shared experiences and that makes us technologically powerful in a new way and philosophically different from what we were before. ] Yes, the shared tradition phrase that you added there, that’s an important one. So I’d say in the early modern world there’s not necessarily a skepticism about shared traditions—so there would be an acceptance of shared traditions—but the idea is that you would not uncritically accept your tradition. You may accept your tradition, but only after you've thought it through and made your own independent judgment. Okay, okay, so you’re elevated to the status of someone who’s capable of taking a stance with regards to the tradition, and assessing its presuppositions and so forth. Absolutely. So there’s an elevation of the individual and the critical intellect along with the elaboration of the scientific method. Okay, so then we might note, perhaps, that that’s a tremendously effective transformation, although maybe it leads in a somewhat nihilistic direction metaphysically—we can leave that to the side. But it’s a very, very successful revolution, because by the time, at least the beginning of the 20th century comes along, there’s this staggering (and of course before that, the Industrial Revolution), there’s this staggering transformation of technology and technological and conceptual power, and then a stunning increase in the standard of living. And that starts at about 1890, to really move exponentially in the 1890s, or at least to get to the really steep part of the exponential curve. Okay, so that seems to be going well. So what is it that the postmodernists are objecting to precisely? Just on those two issues: (1) the metaphysical naturalism, and then (2) the elevation of kind of a critical empiricism and a belief that we can, through science—even not necessarily a science, but social scientists and so on—we can come to understand powerful general principles about humanity and social systems. Those two revolutions both are then subjected to counter-attacks. And again, what happens in this case is there is a revolution. Probably by the time we get to 1800—the height of the Enlightenment—there are the beginnings of more powerful skeptical traditions that come to be developed, so thinkers are starting to say things like: Well, if scientific method at root is based on the evidence of the senses—we observe the natural world: that’s our first point of contact—and then on the basis of that we form abstractions, and then we put those abstractions into propositions, and then we take those propositions and put them in networks that we call theories, and so on—so we start to critically examine each of the elements of scientific method, and over time, weaknesses in the existing accounts of how all of those “rational operations” work come to be teased out, and philosophy then starts to go down a more skeptical path. So if, for example, you take perception as fundamental—it’s you know, the individual subject’s first point of contact with the natural world—then you have to immediately deal with issues of perceptual illusions, or the possibility that people will have hallucinations, or that the way you report your perceptual experience is at odds with how I report my perceptual experience. Tell me if I’ve got this right. So, with the dawning of the “Empirical Age,” let’s say, there’s this idea that you can derive valid information from sense data—especially if you contrast that sense data rigorously with that of others—okay? So that’s sort of the foundation for the scientific method in some sense. But then—I think this is with Immanuel Kant—there’s an objection to that, which is that, Well, you can’t make the presupposition that that sense data enters your cognitive apparatus, your apparatus of understanding, without a priori structuring, and it seems to me that that’s where the postmodernists really go after the modernists. It’s that, given that you have to have a very complex perceptual structure (that modern people might say was instantiated as a consequence of biological evolution), you can’t make the case that what you’re receiving from the external world is something like “pure information”: it’s always subject—to some very-difficult-to-delimit degree—to “interpretation.” And then you also have to take into account the fact of that a priori structure and what it might mean for your concept of “objective reality.” And that’s Kant, I think, if I’ve got that right. Right. Well, the postmodernists will use both of