Subtitles section Play video
-
Okay, I have a hypothetical situation for you – and you need to make a choice.
-
Listen carefully.
-
You’ve just visited the doctor and she told you you’re going to die unless you get treated
-
immediately.
-
There are two treatments -
-
The blue pill would give you a 100% chance of living another 12 years before dying, and
-
the red pill would give you an 89% chance of living another 12 years, a 10% chance of
-
living another 18 years and a 1% chance of sudden death.
-
Which do you choose?
-
Now remember your answer, and imagine a slightly different scenario.
-
Your regular doctor is out that day so you go to the slightly dodgier one next door,
-
who offers you two other treatments:
-
The green pill gives you an 11% chance of living 12 years before dying and an 89% chance
-
of sudden death, and the yellow pill gives you a 10% chance of living a full 18 years
-
before dying, with a 90% chance of sudden death.
-
So, which one of these do you choose?
-
So what did you base your decisions on?
-
Behavioural economists think we make decisions based on something called expected utility
-
– it’s how much we expect that something will satisfy our wants and needs.
-
If you like chocolate ice cream more than vanilla, you’ll feel more satisfied if you
-
choose chocolate (in the animation both ice creams have cherries on top (I’ll come back
-
to this)).
-
So for you, chocolate ice cream has more expected utility.
-
Studies show that in the previous question most people choose the blue pill in the first
-
scenario, giving them a guarantee of living another 12 years, and the yellow pill in the
-
second scenario, giving them a 10% chance of living another 18 years, and a 90% chance
-
of death.
-
But what if instead we write the options out like this:
-
Now the options have something in common.
-
In the first scenario, in both cases you have an 89% chance of living 12 years, so if we
-
remove that, your decision shouldn’t change, right?
-
Kind of like how removing a cherry from both ice creams won’t change your favorite flavor.
-
In the second scenario, both options have an 89% chance of death in common, so we should
-
be able to cancel those too without changing your decision.
-
Hold on, now both scenarios are exactly the same.
-
But studies showed that most people chose the blue pill in the first scenario and the
-
yellow pill in the second one, which doesn’t make sense.
-
Both the blue and green pills give you a higher chance of living over the chance of a longer
-
life, and the red and yellow pills give you a chance of a longer life but with the drawback
-
of a lower chance of living.
-
So for people who chose the blue and yellow pills, what do they want?
-
A higher chance of living or a longer life?
-
This is called the Allais Paradox – it was first outlined by Maurice Allais, a Nobel-Prize
-
winning economist in a 1953 article.
-
The paradox undermines the theory of expected utility because it shows that we don't always
-
make decisions that align with our wants and needs.
-
We tend to make decisions based on how much we think we have to gain or lose now, rather
-
than on the final outcome.
-
And we also tend to choose certainty over risk, even if the riskier option is closer
-
to what we really want.
-
Psychologists who have studied the Allais Paradox found that people dislike risk in
-
general.
-
When questions are framed in terms of gains or losses, people are far more likely to consider
-
the losses first and try to minimise them – it’s a phenomenon called loss aversion.
-
It’s similar to regret theory, which says that when we’re making decisions, some of
-
us try to minimise the amount of regret we feel afterward.
-
Humans are pretty complicated!
-
And not everything is as simple as ice cream.
-
So, what did you decide?