Subtitles section Play video
-
We ended last time talking about the narrative conception of the self.
-
We were testing the narrative conception of the self
-
and the idea of obligations of solidarity or membership
-
that did not flow from consent,
-
that claimed us for reasons unrelated to a contract or an agreement
-
or a choice we may have made.
-
And we were debating among ourselves
-
whether there are any obligations of this kind
-
or whether all apparent obligations of solidarity and membership
-
can be translated into consent or reciprocity
-
or universal duty that we owe persons qua persons.
-
And then there were those who defended the idea of loyalty and of patriotism.
-
So the idea of loyalty and of solidarity and of membership
-
gathered a certain kind of
-
intuitive moral force in our discussion.
-
And then, as we concluded,
-
we considered what seems to be a pretty powerful counter example to that idea.
-
Namely, the film of those southern segregationists in the 1950s.
-
And they talked all about their traditions,
-
their history, the way in which their identities were bound up
-
with their life history. Do you remember that?
-
And what flowed from that history, from that narrative sense of identity
-
for those southern segregationists?
-
They said we have to defend our way of life.
-
Is this a fatal or a decisive objection to the idea
-
of the narrative conception of the self?
-
That’s the question we were left with.
-
What I would like to do today
-
is to advance an argument and see what you make of it.
-
And let me tell you what that argument is.
-
I would like to defend
-
the narrative conception of the person
-
as against the voluntarist conception.
-
I would like to defend
-
the idea that there are obligations of solidarity or membership.
-
Then, I want to suggest
-
that there being such obligations
-
lends force to the idea, when we turn to justice,
-
that arguments about justice can’t be detached,
-
cannot be detached after all, from questions of the good.
-
But I wanted to distinguish two different ways
-
in which justice might be tied to the good
-
and argue for one of them.
-
Now, the voluntarist conception of the person of Kant and Rawls
-
we saw was powerful and liberating.
-
A further appeal is its universal aspiration.
-
The idea of treating persons as persons
-
without prejudice, without discrimination,
-
and I think that’s what led some among us to argue that,
-
okay, maybe there are obligations of membership but they are always subordinate.
-
They must always be subordinate
-
to the duties that we have to human beings as such, the universal duties.
-
But is that right?
-
If our encompassing loyalty should always take precedence
-
over more particular ones,
-
then the distinction between friends and strangers
-
should ideally be overcome.
-
A special concern for the welfare of friends would be a kind of prejudice,
-
a measure of our distance from universal human concern
-
But if you look closely at that idea,
-
what kind of a moral universe, what kind of moral imagination,
-
would that lead you to?
-
The enlightenment flows from Montesquieu
-
gives perhaps the most powerful, and I think,
-
the ultimately, the most honest account
-
of where this relentless universalizing tendency
-
leads the moral imagination.
-
Here’s how Montesquieu put it.
-
He said, "A truly virtuous man would come to the aid
-
of the most distant stranger as quickly as to his own friend."
-
And then he adds, listen to this,
-
"If men were perfectly virtuous, they wouldn't have friends."
-
But it’s difficult to imagine a world
-
in which persons were so virtuous that they had no friends,
-
only a universal disposition to friendliness.
-
The problem isn’t simply that such a world
-
would be difficult to bring about, that it's unrealistic.
-
The deeper problem is that such a world
-
would be difficult to recognize as a human world.
-
The love of humanity is a noble sentiment
-
but most of the time we live our lives by smaller solidarities.
-
This may reflect certain limits to the bounds of moral sympathy,
-
but more important, it reflects the fact
-
that we learn to love humanity, not in general,
-
but through its particular expressions.
-
So these are some considerations.
-
They’re not knock-down arguments,
-
but moral philosophy can’t offer knock-down arguments,
-
but considerations, of the kinds that we've been
-
discussing and arguing about all along.
-
Well, suppose that’s right.
-
One way of assessing whether this picture of the person
-
and of obligation is right, is to see
-
what are its consequences for justice.
-
And here is where is confronts a serious problem,
-
and here we go back to our southern segregationists.
-
They felt the weight of history.
-
Do we admire their character, these segregationists,
-
who wanted to preserve their way of life?
-
Are we committed to saying,
-
if we accept the idea of solidarity and membership,
-
are we committed to saying
-
that justice is tied to good in the sense that justice means
-
whatever a particular community or tradition says it means,
-
including those southern segregationists.
-
Here it’s important to distinguish two different ways
-
in which justice can be tied to the good.
-
One is a relativist way.
-
That’s the way that says,
-
to think about rights, to think about justice,
-
look to the values that happened to prevail
-
in any given community at any given time.
-
Don’t judge them by some outside standard,
-
but instead conceive justice as a matter of being faithful to the shared understandings
-
of a particular tradition.
-
But there’s a problem with this way of tying justice to the good.
-
The problem is that it makes justice wholly conventional.
-
A product of circumstance,
-
and this deprives justice of its critical character.
-
But there is a second way in which
-
justice can be tied with or bound up with the good.
-
On a second non-relativist way of linking justice with conceptions of the good,
-
principles of justice depend for their justification not on the values
-
that happened to prevail at any given moment in a certain place,
-
but instead on the moral worth or the intrinsic good of the ends rights serve.
-
On this non-relativist view the case for recognizing a right
-
depends on showing that it
-
honors or advances some important human good.
-
The second way of tying justice to the good
-
is not strictly speaking, communitarian,
-
if by communitarian you mean,
-
just giving over to a particular community the definition of justice.
-
Now, what I would like to suggest
-
that of these two different ways of linking justice to the good,
-
the first is insufficient.
-
Because the first leaves justice the creature of convention.
-
It doesn't give us enough
-
moral resources to respond to those southern segregationists
-
who invoke their way of life, their traditions,
-
their way of doing things.
-
But if justice is bound up with the good in a non-relativist way,
-
there is a big challenge, a big question to answer.
-
How can we reason about the good?
-
What about the fact that people hold different conceptions of the good?
-
Different ideas about the purposes of key social institutions.
-
Different ideas about what social goods and human goods
-
are worthy of honor and recognition.
-
We live in a pluralist society, people disagree about the good.
-
That’s one of the incentives to try to find principles of justice
-
and rights that don’t depend
-
on any particular ends or purposes or goods.
-
So is there a way to reason about the good?
-
Before addressing that question,
-
I want to address a slightly easier question.
-
Is it necessary, is it unavoidable, when arguing about justice
-
to argue about the good?
-
And my answer to that question is yes, it’s unavoidable.
-
It's necessary.
-
So for the remainder of today, I want to take up...
-
I want to try to advance that claim,
-
that reasoning about the good, about purposes, and ends,
-
is an unavoidable feature of arguing about justice,
-
it’s necessary.
-
Let me see if I can establish that.
-
And for that I’d like for us to begin a discussion of same sex marriage.
-
Now, same sex marriage draws on, implicateds,
-
deeply contested and controversial ideas,
-
morally and religiously.
-
And so there’s a powerful incentive
-
to embrace a conception of justice or of rights
-
that doesn’t require the society as a whole to pass judgment,
-
one way or another,
-
on those hotly contested moral and religious questions.
-
About the moral permissibility of homosexuality.
-
About the proper ends of marriage as a social institution.
-
So, clearly, if there’s an incentive to resolve this question,
-
to define people’s rights in a way that doesn’t require the society as a whole
-
to sort out those moral and religious disputes
-
that would be very attractive.
-
So what I would like to do now is to see,
-
using the same sex marriage case,
-
whether it’s possible to detach one’s use
-
about the moral permissibility of homosexuality and about
-
the purpose, the end of marriage,
-
detach those questions from the question of
-
whether the state should recognize same sex marriage or not.
-
So let's begin.
-
I would like to begin by hearing the arguments of those
-
who believe that there should be no same sex marriage
-
but that the state should only recognize marriage between a man and a woman.
-
Do I have volunteers? I had two.
-
There were two people I asked,
-
people who had voiced their views already on the justice blog.
-
Mark Loff and Ryan McCaffrey where are you?
-
Okay, Mark. And where is Ryan?
-
Alright, let’s go first to Mark.
-
I have sort of a theological understanding of
-
the purpose of sex and the purpose of marriage.
-
And I think that for people like myself, who are a a Christian and also a Catholic,
-
the purpose of sex is, one, for its procreative uses,
-
and two, for a unifying purpose between a man and a woman
-
within the institution of marriage.
-
You have a certain conception of the purpose or the telos... - Yeah.
-
...of human sexuality, which is bound up with procreation.
-
Right.
-
As well as union. - Yeah.
-
And the essence of marriage, the purpose of marriage as a social institution
-
is to give expression to that telos
-
and to honor that purpose, namely, the procreative purpose of marriage.
-
Is that a fair summary of your view? - Yeah.
-
Where is Ryan? Go ahead.
-
Do you agree more or less with Mark’s reasons?
-
Yes, I agree.
-
I think that the ideal of marriage involves procreation.
-
And it’s fine that, homosexuals would go off and cohabitate with each other
-
but the government doesn’t have a responsibility to encourage that.
-
All right, so the government should not encourage
-
homosexual behavior by conferring the recognition of marriage.
-
Yeah, it would be wrong to outlaw it but encouraging it is not necessary.
-
Who has a reply?
-
Yes.
-
Hannah?
-
I just like to ask a question to Mark.
-
Let’s say you got married to a woman,
-
you did not have sex with her before marriage,
-
and then when you became married it became evident that
-
you’re an infertile couple.
-
Do you think that it should illegal for you to engage in sex
-
if children will not result from that act?
-
Yeah, I think that it is moral and that’s why I gave the two-fold purpose.
-
So like a woman, say...
-
I think older couples can get married,
-
someone... a woman who’s beyond...
-
she has already had menopause and who can’t have a child,
-
because I think that sex has these...
-
It has purposes beyond procreation.
-
I hate to be uncouth but have you ever engaged in masturbation?
-
You don’t have to answer that.
-
Right, make your...
-
I’d like to respond to that.
-
Wait. We’ve done pretty well over a whole semester
-
and we’re doing pretty well now dealing with
-
questions that most people think can’t even be discussed to any university settting
-
and, Hannah, you’ve got, you have a powerful point.
-
Make that point as a general argument rather than,